HEURISTICS FOR DECISIONS UNDER UNKNOWN PROBABILITIES
▪ Maximin: maximize the minimum payoff
▪ Maximax: maximize the maximum gain
▪ Least regret rule (Savage-Niehans): max regret I could have by choosing this
▪ Based on regrets for each choice option ▪ I.e. relate each payoff of the respective choice alternative (e.g., investment levels or different projects) to the best possible outcome at a specific state of nature (e.g., prices or weather) → the difference is the regret. ▪ Find for each alternative the maximum regret. ▪ Choose alternative minimizing regret ▪ Hurwicz rule:
▪ Intuition: mix of optimism and pessimism ▪ Define: optimism parameter 𝜆 and respective pessimism parameter 1 − 𝜆 →the smaller the parameter is, the more risk averse is the decision-maker ▪ Define Hurwicz-criterion H for each possible action a (investment alternative) while weighting the possible states i subjectively ▪ Decision rule: Maximize 𝐻𝑎 = 𝜆max + (1 − 𝜆)min EXPECTED UTILITY THEORY
expected payout in the expected outcome Problem: just to rely on expeced returns disregards preferences for outcomes and risk exposure under different alternatives Expected utility framework (EU):
▪ Preferences for possible outcomes
▪ Pay-off in terms of expected utility (EU) ▪ Idea of John von Neumann & Oskar Morgenstern (1944)
with mathematical basis for economic decision making
and the thus far predominant approach in agricultural economics An example-coin toss: heads→100€, tails→0€ 𝑒𝑖 = {h𝑒𝑎𝑑𝑠 𝑡𝑎𝑖𝑙𝑠
• 𝑎 (h𝑒𝑎𝑑𝑠)= 100€, 𝑎(𝑡𝑎𝑖𝑙𝑠)= 0€
• Pr (𝑎 (h𝑒𝑎𝑑𝑠))= Pr (𝑎 (𝑡𝑎𝑖𝑙𝑠))= 0.5
• Wecanwrite:𝐸𝑈(𝑎)= 0.5𝑈(𝑎(h𝑒𝑎𝑑𝑠))+0.5𝑈(𝑎(𝑡𝑎𝑖𝑙𝑠))=0.5𝑈(0)+0.5𝑈(100)
• Note: E(U) model is linear in probabilities
▪ Monetary rewards are represented by a random variable Z 𝑎 𝑒𝑖 = Z
▪ Decision maker decides between risky prospects, has preferences towards these actions:
𝑎1~𝑎2, 𝑎1 ≺ 𝑎2 or 𝑎1 ≻ 𝑎2
▪ Link to observed decisions: 𝑎1 is chosen over 𝑎2 if 𝑎1 ≿ 𝑎2
▪ Decisions affect the distribution of the outcome, depending on the states of nature: Z 𝑎 𝑒𝑖
▪ Payoff-valuation: in terms of utility:
Preferences towards risky choices represented with a utility function 𝑈 𝑍 →typically: von Neumann Morgenstern utility function
▪ Decisions based on expected utility
▪Defined:𝐸𝑈 𝑍 =σ𝑖≥1𝑈 𝑍(𝑎 𝑒𝑖 Pr 𝑎 𝑒𝑖 ,
where E is the expectation operator based on subjective probability distributions of Z(𝑎(𝑒𝑖 )) (random reward)
▪ Rational decision maker: will maximize the expected value of her/his utility: expected utility function EU
▪Thisis :max𝐸[𝑈 𝑍 𝑎 𝑒𝑖 =max σ𝑖≥1𝑈 𝑍(𝑎 𝑒𝑖 Pr 𝑎 𝑒𝑖
Preferences
maximizing profit and returns it’s not accounting for preferences different utility functions imply which preferences Expected utility of a random action = utility of the certainty equivalent
in the example: General notation for random reward Z
𝐸𝐸𝑈𝑈𝑍𝑍 =𝑈𝑈𝐶𝐶𝐸𝐸 =𝑈𝑈𝐸𝐸𝑍𝑍 −𝑅𝑅𝑅𝑅 <𝑈𝑈(𝐸𝐸𝑍𝑍) If 𝑅𝑅𝑅𝑅 = 0 , the decision maker DM is risk ... 𝑅𝑅𝑅𝑅<0 risk ... Averse (pay someone for taking the risk), neutral, loving (pay someone that gives you his/her risk) The sign of RP is a measure for general notion of risk preferences
But at different points at the risk utility function, different RP-values: e.g., in neighbourhood of the riskless case, the RP is proportional to the variance of Z → incomplete measure for risk preferences → better: coefficients of risk aversion COEFFICIENT OF RISK AVERSION BY ARROW PRATT Measuringtheeffectof𝑉𝑉𝑎𝑎𝑉𝑉𝑍𝑍 ontheriskpremium:Arrow-Prattriskaversioncoefficient: 𝑉𝑉 ≡ − 𝑈𝑈′′ Links to earlier assumptions on shapes of utility function: Concavity implies risk aversion: 𝑈𝑈′′ <0and𝑈𝑈′ >0 →𝑉𝑉>0 Convexity of 𝑈𝑈(�) implies: 𝑈𝑈′ >0and𝑈𝑈′′ >0 →𝑉𝑉<0
Jensen’s inequality provides global properties RELATIVE COEFFICIENT OF RISK AVERSION Search for a measure of risk aversion independent on units of measurement Relative Risk Premium: 𝑅𝑅𝑅𝑅 = 𝑅𝑅𝑅𝑅 is the proportion (ratio) of the risk premium in relation to expected
(terminal) wealth
Arrow-Pratt coefficient of relative risk aversion
𝐸𝐸(𝑥𝑥)
′′
𝑉𝑉̅ ≡ 𝑉𝑉 � 𝑍𝑍 = − 𝑈𝑈 /𝑈𝑈𝑈 𝑍𝑍
Interpret Z as the level of total income For risk aversion: 𝑉𝑉 and 𝑉𝑉̅ are both positive, where 𝑉𝑉 is more common 16
RISK PREFERENCES AND LEVEL OF INCOME
r can be constant, increasing or decreasing in Z (changes in r with higher absolute Z):
Constant Absolute Risk AversionCARA Increasing Absolute Risk AversionIARA Decrasing Absolute Risk AversionDARA
Similar for 𝑉𝑉̅ (proportional changes in 𝑉𝑉̅ to Z): CRRA, IRRA, DRRA
INTERPRETATION AND RELATION COEFFICIENTS Constant Relative Risk Aversion (CRRA): 𝑉𝑉̅ is independent of terminal wealth
i.e. preferences among risky prospects are unchanged if all payoffs are multiplied by a positive constant Constant Absolute Risk Aversion (CARA): preferences are unchanged if a constant amount is added to or subtracted from all payoffs Remember, constant and relative risk aversion coefficients are linked: 𝑉𝑉̅ ≡ 𝑉𝑉 � 𝑍𝑍
For example, constant relative risk aversion (CRRA) implies decreasing absolute risk aversion (DARA)! IMPORTANT CASE: DECREASING ABSOLUTE RISK AVERSION Willingness to take risk decreases with total income level DARA implies 𝑈𝑈𝑈𝑈𝑈 > 0 (aversion against downside risk) otherwise it would not be strictly decreasing (see appendix and Chavas for details) What does it mean to have strictly decreasing absolute risk aversion? Not only variance matters – also higher order moments! Skewness! Degree of decrease in risk aversion determines whether CRRA, DRRA or IRRA A and B have the same mean and variance,
but A has the more negative skewness more skewed to the left, i.e. more exposure to downside risk compared to B Given the EU concept, B will be preferred over A iff 𝑼𝑼𝑈𝑈′ > 𝟎𝟎 (iff the DM has aversion against downside risk) CARA or DARA seem plausible
DARA is the dominant empirical observation made Exclude Quadratic: too unrealisitic (IARA)
RP sign is not enough to understand all complexity of DM beavior. ARA and RRA helps to diffentiate behavior of DM based on Z variance, Z is initial wealth for example
r can be constant, increasing or decreasing in Z (changes in r with higher absolute Z):
CARA - Constant Absolute Risk Aversion IARA - Increasing Absolute Risk Aversion DARA - Decrasing Absolute Risk Aversion, DARA empirically mostly observed – for relative risk aversion less clear! Similar for rr (proportional changes in rr to Z):
CRRA - Constant Relative Risk Aversion IRRA - Increasing Relative Risk Aversion DRRA- Decrasing Relative Risk Aversion
Example lecture, heristics
Example, taken from Musshow/Hirschauer 2009: Modernes Agrarmanagement. 4. Auflage
maximin = A2 Rye / Rent
maximax = A1 Wheat
Heurits = A2 Rye
What is the preferred option, using the Maximin, Maximax, Hurwicz, Least-regret rules?
Least regrets - A1 Wheat
HEURISTICS FOR DECISIONS UNDER UNKNOWN PROBABILITIES - CRITICISM
▪ Only provides decision rules “cooking recipes”
▪ Answers might be inconsistent
▪ No theoretical foundation
▪ Not clear what underlying preferences are
Example lecture, sure income, random reward, including graph CE, RP
▪ Get some intuition why risk utility function represents risk preferences
▪ Stick to risk aversion
Illustration
Consider the following situation with two alternatives:
▪ 𝑃𝑜𝑠𝑠𝑖𝑏𝑙𝑒 𝐴𝑐𝑡𝑖𝑜𝑛 1 (𝑎1) :sure income, denote by 𝑍0 ,which gives: 𝐸 𝑍 𝑎1 = 𝑍0
▪ 𝑃𝑜𝑠𝑠𝑖𝑏𝑙𝑒 𝐴𝑐𝑡𝑖𝑜𝑛 2 (𝑎2) :income is random reward, you know with 50% probability you get 𝑍+ and 𝑍− , respectively
that is: Pr(𝑍+) = Pr(𝑍−) = 0.5
but same expected value 𝐸 𝑍 𝑎2 = 𝐸 𝑍 𝑎1 (15 euro) = 𝑍0
▪ So for example 15 (a1) = 0.5*10 + 0.5*20 (a2) =5+10 = 15
𝑎1: sure income, denote by 𝑍0, which gives: 𝐸 𝑍 𝑎1 = 𝑍0
𝑎2: random reward, but equally likely
Now:
1.) Take 5min yourself to understand the graphical representation on the next two slides.
2.) Then make groups (all people in a row) – try to explain the graph to each other in the groups.
How many imes you play and what is my goal? + what ius my financial resilience? Can I let myself loose 5 euro?
E[U(z1))=U(Z0) higher?
E[U(Z2)] = U(CE)
Example lecture E(U) on agriculture example Wheat, Rye, Rent out
▪ There are 3 options to be considered by the farmer: grow mainly wheat, mainly rye, or rent out the land
▪ Recall: heuristics delivered no clear result*
▪ Presume exponential risk utility function:
𝑈(𝑍) =𝛼−𝛽∙exp( −𝜆∙𝑍) with 𝛼=5, 𝛽=200 and 𝜆=0.3 (we can find out parameteres for risks for each preferences with survey or games)
▪ To get E(U) = 0.3*U(Zlow)+0.5*U(Zmed)+0.2*U(Zhigh)
▪Get CE by using inverse of the utility function: 𝑍 𝑈 = −ln
▪Evaluate inverse at 𝐸 𝑈 : use 𝑍(𝐸(𝑈)) = 𝐶𝐸
▪E.g. for action rye: 𝑍 3.98 = −ln 5−3.98 1 = 17.60
▪Get the RP by difference between expected value and certainty equivalent
▪I.e.: 𝑅𝑃 = 𝐸(𝑍) − 𝐶𝐸
▪E.g. 𝑅𝑃_𝑟𝑦𝑒 = 18 − 17.60 = 0.4
Trial exam 2025 Q1.1 + Q3 + Q4
Given:
Assuming positive wealth, people that are risk averse always have a negative risk premium o True
o False
o We cannot say it depends on the certainty equivalent
Complete the following sentences: (3 Points) If the risk premium = 0, the decision maker is risk neutral, linear
If the risk premium > 0, the decision maker is risk averse, convex
If the risk premium < 0, the decision maker is risk loving, concave
risk premium - negative, positive or 0? What needs to be answered here:
relationships between risk behavior preferences and the risk premium Visualize task with scheme, picture, short mathematical writing or table:
Formulas to use:
Solution:
False, Yes, a risk-averse individual will always have a positive risk premium, regardless of their initial wealth. While the magnitude of the risk premium can depend on initial wealth for certain types of risk preferences (e.g., it decreases with wealth under decreasing absolute risk aversion, DARA, or increases under increasing absolute risk aversion, IARA), its fundamental positive sign for a risk-averse individual does not change. In the specific case of Constant Absolute Risk Aversion (CARA) preferences, the risk premium R is explicitly independent of initial wealth w. This implies that if a CARA individual is risk-averse, their positive risk premium will persist irrespective of their wealth level. If the ARA or r or risk premium = 0, the decision maker is risk neutral, linear If the ARA or r or risk premium > 0, the decision maker is risk averse, convex
If the ARA or r or risk premium < 0, the decision maker is risk loving, concave
▪ r > 0: Corresponds to risk-averse behavior and a concave utility function (U'' < 0), indicating decreasing marginal utility of wealth. ▪ r = 0: Corresponds to risk-neutral behavior and a linear utility function (U'' = 0), implying constant marginal utility. ▪ r < 0: Corresponds to risk-loving behavior and a convex utility function (U'' > 0), indicating increasing marginal utility. this is because "in the small" (i.e., in the neighborhood of the riskless case, using a Taylor series expansion), the sign of the risk premium R is always the same as the sign of r In essence, the risk premium provides a monetary measure of the cost or benefit of bearing risk, while the Arrow-Pratt coefficient provides a standardized, unit-independent measure of the underlying risk preference (the curvature of the utility function) that drives that cost or benefit. They are two sides of the same coin in evaluating how individuals react to uncertainty. The risk premium (R) is defined as the sure amount of money a decision-maker (DM) would be willing to forgo to avoid a risky prospect and instead receive its expected value.
◦ It represents the "shadow cost of private risk bearing" or an individual's "willingness to insure" aka willigness to risk, willignes to take risk, willigness to take on risk Given:
Q4: Suppose a decision maker has the following von Neumann Morgenstern utility function: 𝑼(𝒙) = 𝐥n(𝟑𝒙^2). What can you say about her absolute and relative risk aversion coefficients, and what type of preferences do they imply? Justify and briefly explain your statements. (4 Points) von Neumann Morgenstern utility function: 𝑼(𝒙) = 𝐥n(𝟑𝒙^2) What needs to be answered here:
What can you say about her absolute and relative risk aversion coefficients, and what type of preferences do they imply? Justify and briefly explain your statements. Visualize task with scheme, picture, short mathematical writing or table:
if r is positive then it’s risk aversion (U’’ <0, and U’>0) if r is negative then it’s risk loving (U’>0 and U’’>0) Micro slides, rules derivations Solution:
U’=d𝐥n(𝟑𝒙^2)/dx = 1/(3x^2)*6x=6x/3x^2=26x/3x^21=2/x=2*x^-1 >0 U’’=d(2x^-1)/dx=-1*2*x^-2=-2*x^-2 <0 r=-U’’/U’=-(-12*x^-21)/(2*x^-1)=-(-1*x^-1)=x^-1 or 1/x > 0 if r is positive then it’s risk aversion (U’’ <0, and U’>0) → DARA and risk averse rr=rx(or Z) = x^-1*x=x^-1*x = 1 → rr=1 →CRRA where rr is relarive risk aversion coefficient x or Z level of total outcome aka our variable Trial exam 2025 Q6
Trial exam 2025 Q7
Practical 3, A1: Drought risk in crop production
Practical 3, A2: Start-up investment
Practical 3, A3: Coefficients of risk aversion
Practical 3, A4: Certainty equivalent
Practical 3, A5 Open question Charlie owns a house worth 300,000€. There is a probability equal to 0.05 that the house will burn
down completely in a fire. He can insure his house against a loss from this fire. The premium for
full insurance is 17,000€. Additionally Charlie has wealth equal to 100,000€ in non- risky assets.
1. If he had v.N-M utility function 𝑢(𝑥) = √𝑥 ,would he buy this full insurance policy? Which is
the maximum premium that he is willing to pay for full insurance?
2. If, instead, he had v.N-M utility function 𝑢(𝑥) = 𝑙𝑛(𝑥), which would be the maximum
premium that he would be willing to pay for full insurance?
3. How do these findings correspond with your findings in Q2?
E(𝑈(𝑥)) = 0.95* √400000 + 0.05 * √100000 = 616.64 → Without insurance: 𝐸(𝑥) = 400,000 * 0.95 + 100,000 * 0.05 = 385,000
→ With insurance: 𝐸(𝑥) = 400,000 − 17,000 = 383,000 →From having the insurance, the
expected wealth is reduced by 2000€. Thus, this is not a ‘fair’ premium. If the
decision maker would not be risk averse, she would not buy the insurance!
thus 𝑈(𝐸(𝑥)) = √385000 = 620,48
The maximum premium m is:
𝐸(𝑈(𝑥)) = 616.64 and 𝑢(𝑥) = √𝑥
thus 𝑥 = 616.642 = 380,244.89
𝑅𝑃 = 385,000 − 380,244.89 = 4,755.11
As this additional value given by the risk averse decision maker is larger than the
‘price’ in terms of reduced wealth, she would buy the insurance.
2. → 𝐸(𝑈(𝑥)) = 0.95𝑙𝑛(400000) + 0.05𝑙𝑛(100000) = 12.83 , and 𝑈(𝐸(𝑥)) = 𝑙𝑛(385000) = 12.860 he would also buy that insurance policy when 𝑢(𝑥) = 𝑙𝑛(𝑥)
The maximum premium m is:
𝐸𝑈(𝑥) = 12.83 and 𝑢(𝑥) = 𝑙𝑛(𝑥) thus 𝑥 = 𝑒12.83 = 373248.61
𝑅𝑃 = 385,000 – 373,248.61 = 11,751.39 The individual is willing to pay more for full insurance
when 𝑢(𝑥) = 𝑙𝑛(𝑥).
3. An individual with 𝑢(𝑥) = 𝑙𝑛𝑥 is more risk averse than an individual with and 𝑢(𝑥) = √𝑥, as
ARA[ln(𝑥)] =
1
𝑥
>
1
2𝑥 =ARA(√𝑥), and, therefore, is willing to pay more for full insurance (the risk
premium of the risky alternative is greater for an individual with 𝑢(𝑥) = √𝑥 than for an
individual with 𝑢(𝑥) = 𝑙𝑛(𝑥)).
Given:
Charlie owns a house worth 300,000€. There is a probability equal to 0.05=5% that the house will burn down completely in a fire. He can insure his house against a loss from this fire. The premium for full insurance is 17,000€. Condition: Additionally Charlie has wealth equal to 100,000€ in non-risky assets. What needs to be answered here:
If he had v.N-M utility function 𝑢(𝑥) = √𝑥 ,would he buy this full insurance policy? Condition: v.N-M utility function 𝑢(𝑥) = √𝑥 Which is the maximum premium that he is willing to pay for full insurance? If, instead, he had v.N-M utility function 𝑢(𝑥) = 𝑙𝑛(𝑥), which would be the maximum
premium that he would be willing to pay for full insurance? Condition: v.N-M utility function 𝑢(𝑥) = 𝑙𝑛(𝑥) How do these findings correspond with your findings in Q2 (Q1?)?
Visualize task with scheme, picture, short mathematical writing or table:
Formulas to use:
where: